Paper Status Tracking
Contact us
[email protected]
Click here to send a message to me 3275638434
Paper Publishing WeChat

Article
Affiliation(s)

Noboss, Kent, UK

ABSTRACT

How is the significance of the doctrine Scientism to be understood? To answer that question, it will be necessary to distinguish three stances towards scientific activity. This can be done by developing distinctions already delineated between Relativistic, Methodological and Dogmatic Scientism. In the present paper, the first two senses are best characterized as the scientistic: Scientistic Relativism and Scientistic Methodologism. Dogmatic Scientism arises in two forms: a Janus-faced Scientism and an Essentialist form. The former can be understood as advocating a public tolerance of behaviourism in relation to other people’s responses, cast as spatio-temporal events whilst adopting, at the same time, a private existentialism so that one’s own first person evaluations remain valid. An Essentialist form sustains a predictive and normative stance where any human action or communication is cast as “a natural object of investigation of the empirical sciences”. After distinguishing these four ways of interpreting scientific activity, Ladyman and Ross’s own contribution to this debate can be elucidated through examining five theses carried by their text Every Thing Must Go, and ideas forwarded subsequently in Ladyman’s article “Scientism with a Humane Face”: (1) the attack upon conceptual analysis; (2) the defence of metaphysics; (3) the advocacy of scale relative ontology; (4) the rehabilitation of Peirce’s philosophy; and (5) the rejection of a traditional conception of materialism. It may then become possible to ascertain how far their approach to scientific activity can be identified with either a Scientific Methodologism or some form of Scientism itself.

KEYWORDS

relativism, scientific, scientistic, scientism, Janus faced, essentialist

Cite this paper

Sociology Study, July-Aug. 2020, Vol. 10, No. 4, 173-183

References

Apel, K.-O. (1980). Towards a transformation of philosophy. (G. Adey & D. Frisby, Trans.). London: Routledge & K. Paul.

Apel, K.-O. (1984). Understanding and explanation. (G. Warnke, Trans.). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Apel, K.-O. (1995). Charles S. Peirce: From pragmatism to pragmaticism. Amherst: University of Massachusetts Press.

Boulting, N. E. (2015). Scale relative ontology and scientism. Philosophica, 46, 99-118.

Chakravartty, A. (2007). Six degrees of speculation. In B. Monton (Ed.), Images of empiricism: Essays on science and stances, with a reply from Bas C. van Fraassen (pp. 183-208). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Chakravartty, A. (2013). On the prospects of naturalized metaphysics. In D. Ross, J. Ladyman, and H. Kincaid (Eds.), Scientific metaphysics (pp. 27-50). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Feyerabend, P. K. (1981). Materialism and the mind-body problem. In Realism, rationalism and scientific method (pp. 161-175). Cambridge University Press.

Feyerabend, P. K. (1987). Farewell to reason. London: Verso.

Gehlen, A. (1980). Man in the age of technology. (P. Lipscomb, Trans.). New York: Columbia University Press.

Haack, S. (2013). Putting philosophy to work. New York: Prometheus Books.

Habermas, J. (1972). Knowledge and human interests. Boston: Beacon Press.

Habermas, J. (1979). Communication & the evolution of society. (T. McCarthy, Trans.). Boston: Beacon Press.

Habermas, J. (1982). A reply to my critics. In J. B. Thompson and D. Held (Eds.), Habermas—Critical debates. London: Macmillan.

Hungerland, L., & Vick, G. R. (1973). Hobbes’s theory of signification. Journal of the History of Philosophy, 11(4), 459-482.

Ihde, D. (1991). Instrumental realism. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

Kass, L. (1985). Toward a more natural science. New York: Free Press.

Kass, L. (2002). Life, liberty and the defence of dignity: The challenge of bioethics. San Francisco: Encounter Books.

Ladyman, J. (2002). Understanding philosophy of science. London: Routledge.

Ladyman, J. (2018). Scientism with a humane face. In J. de Ridder, R. Peels, and R. van Woudenberg (Eds.), Scientism: Prospects and problems (pp. 106-126). New York: Oxford University Press.

Ladyman, J., & Ross, D. (2010). Every thing must go: Metaphysics naturalized. New York: Oxford University Press.

Ladyman, J., & Ross, D. (2013). The world in the data. In D. Ross, J. Ladyman, and H. Kincaid (Eds.), Scientific metaphysics (pp. 108-150). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Latour, B. (1987). Science in action. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

Popper, K. (1976). Unended quest. Glasgow: Fontana/Collins.

Santmire, H. P. (1973). Historical dimensions of the American crisis. In I. G. Barbour (Ed.), Western man & environmental ethics. Boston, MA: Addison Wesley.

Stenmark, M. (2001). Scientism: Science, ethics and religion. Aldershot, UK: Ashgate.

Thompson, M. (1978). Peirce’s verificationist realism. Review of Metaphysics, 32(1), 74-98.

Whitehead, A. N. (1933). Adventures of ideas. London: Macmillan.

Whitehead, A. N. (1964). Study of the past. In Science & philosophy. New Jersey: Littlefield, Adams & Co.

About | Terms & Conditions | Issue | Privacy | Contact us
Copyright © 2001 - David Publishing Company All rights reserved, www.davidpublisher.com
3 Germay Dr., Unit 4 #4651, Wilmington DE 19804; Tel: 1-323-984-7526; Email: [email protected]